If you take a moment and observe our current climate, truth is more of a popularity contest. Just take a look at your feed. The typical feed consists of what is accepted and what is agreed upon. And what is agreed upon is typically what is most convenient, least offensive, or loudest. It overlooks a very quiet distinction that has been lost in modern discourse, the difference between coherence and consensus.
These two often look the same. Both produce agreement. Both can give rise to systems of belief, governance, or cooperation. But one builds lasting order, while the other eventually collapses into contradiction and chaos.
Consensus is agreement across a group. It reflects what the majority believes, prefers, or feels. In democratic societies, consensus is often seen as the gold standard. If most people agree then it must be right, or at least good enough to act on.
But consensus is fragile. It fluctuates with time, trends, and incentives. People agree because of shared bias, groupthink, fear of exclusion, or lack of understanding. When the pressure shifts, so does the agreement.
Consensus is inherently self-referential, it validates a position based on the number of adherents, not its alignment with anything beyond the system itself. It creates an echo chamber that rewards conformity over clarity.
Coherence, by contrast, measures the internal and external consistency of ideas. A coherent belief system doesn’t just align people with each other, it aligns them with reality. It checks whether a claim fits within a structured, rational framework that withstands contradiction, distortion, or emotional manipulation.
Coherence depends on reference points that are not subject to consensus. These reference points serve as stable criteria by which truth can be tested. In mathematics, these are axioms. In science, constants. In logic, rules of inference. In ethics and metaphysics, coherence has historically depended on God—the constant, stable reference point that grounds reason itself.
Across civilizations, the idea of God was not simply a moral figure or cultural deity. As the “creator,” it always began as the ontological constant, the necessary foundation that made reality measurable by placing a constant upon the analysis of being. God functioned as the ultimate reference point: not an opinion, but the very condition that made reality coherently observable and reasoning possible in the first place.
Over time, the transcendent constant becomes reduced to an optional opinion in the consensus marketplace, a move that strips humanity of the ability to reliably step outside its own biases to reason clearly.
This reduction of God from a transcendent constant to a subjective belief has profound consequences, not just on metaphysics, but on identity, religion, and civilizational coherence.
When God gets reduced to a matter of consensus, religion follows. Rather than aligning individuals and civilizations to a shared, objective reference point, religions get treated as expressions of identity—no different from language, ethnicity, or custom.
The result is that religion no longer gets seen as a way to calibrate one's mind to reality, but rather as a badge of belonging. Faith becomes heritage. Doctrine becomes flavor. Truth becomes relative.
Without a coherent conception of God as a universal constant, religions no longer unify across time and space. They splinter into sects, local traditions, and social movements, each defined not by truth but by affiliation. And affiliation, by nature, excludes.
In contrast, the more objectively coherent a conception of God is, the more capable it becomes of aligning not just individuals, but entire cultures, nations, civilizations, and humanity itself, across time and space.
Across history, it was this single anchoring role of “creator” that allowed faith traditions to ontologically unify empires, inform laws, build moral systems, and offer trans generational stability. It is coherence, not consensus, that gave religion its power to transcend geography and culture.
The deeper problem is that reason alone cannot produce its own coherence. As Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems demonstrated, no system can prove its own consistency from within. Every rational structure needs something outside of itself to justify its validity.
God, in philosophical terms, was never just a supernatural hypothesis. He always began as the non-contingent reference point that allowed reason to break out of self-reference. Without such a constant, even the tools of logic and evidence become circular or arbitrary.
By denying or sidelining God, society attempts to ground reason in shifting sand. We calibrate truth by consensus, morality by preference, and justice by emotion. This leads to relativism, polarization, and institutional distrust.
Therefore, a transcendent constant is not merely a theological idea, it is a logical necessity. It is what allows people to step out of bias, out of inherited narratives and tribal thinking, and recalibrate their beliefs according to something stable and real.
Just as physics requires constants like the speed of light to make sense of the universe, human reasoning requires a metaphysical constant to make sense of values, rights, justice, and existence.
God was that constant, not as a ruler over people, but as the reference point that made all rulers measurable, all truth testable, and all moral claims comparable.
Without that reference point, even our attempts at justice and fairness degrade into performance. We appeal to human rights, but have no basis for them. We demand equality, but can’t define what makes one human worthy of protection in the first place.
So that leads us to democracy. Democracy is often praised for being based on consensus. But democracy without coherence becomes mob rule. It becomes a numbers game, a contest for influence, not a pursuit of truth.
A coherent democracy, on the other hand, is one in which decisions are tethered to stable principles: justice, reason, evidence, rights. These principles don’t change just because a majority wishes it. They are taught, upheld, and protected, even when inconvenient. In order to do so, a true constant must be recognized in order to maintain that stability.
This is why enduring democracies protect the rights of minorities, enforce constitutional limits, and educate their citizens in logic and civic reasoning. These are not acts of consensus, but coherence—aligning governance with enduring structure rather than temporary agreement.
But when consensus replaces coherence as the foundation of democracy, we see its effects quickly: populism, polarization, distrust. It ultimately leads to social decay.
Part of the confusion is that coherence and consensus can look identical, especially in a well-ordered society. When people are educated in coherence and guided by stable reference points, consensus naturally forms around truth. But consensus that arises from coherence is not the same as consensus as a substitute for coherence.
Consensus can mimic coherence, but when stress hits in economic collapse, political crisis, cultural upheaval, it reveals its fragility. People splinter. Reality asserts itself, and systems based only on consensus cannot withstand the pressure.
A civilization cannot survive on consensus alone. Without coherence, it drifts. Ever adjusting, never arriving. What we need is not louder agreement, but deeper alignment with what is. And that requires the courage to step outside our own minds, our own tribes, and our own times, to calibrate ourselves against a fixed point beyond all of them.
That is what God was always meant to be.
Not a god of the gaps, but the constant that made gaps measurable. Not a cultural relic, but the condition that made culture intelligible. Not a private belief, but the ground of universal coherence.
When we reduce God to a consensus object, we collapse religion into identity, truth into opinion, and unity into tribalism.
When we recover God as the necessary condition for thought, we begin to see the world once more with clarity, structure, and sense, bc we prioritize observation ontologically.
In that recovery lies not just the possibility of faith, but the recovery of reason itself.
The essay claims to distinguish coherence from consensus but ultimately replaces ontological grounding with a metaphysical assertion—God—without ever arguing for God’s existence as part of mind-independent reality. This is textbook reification: coherence dressed up as metaphysics.
You rightly identify the dangers of consensus—groupthink, volatility—and correctly define coherence as internal and external consistency. But you then collapse coherence into theological necessity by positing God as the external referent coherence “requires.” That’s the error: taking an abstract structure (coherence) and retrofitting it with a referent (God) without first proving that referent exists.
But coherence must point to what’s self-evident, not imagined. My referents—existence, identity, consciousness—aren’t argued for; they’re the precondition of all argument. “God” isn’t.
It’s as if you’re saying: “Coherence requires an external anchor. Therefore, that anchor is God. Therefore, God is real.” This is pure question-begging. But the axioms are what make questions possible.
You describe coherence as an epistemological process, but treat its conclusion—God—as an ontological given. You’re using the structure of thought to smuggle in a claim about being, without ever demonstrating that the “being” in question is more than a conceptual placeholder.
Even if reason requires a grounding point, you can’t just insert “God” into that role. Ontological reality isn’t established by conceptual need or logical elegance. The referent must be discovered, not posited. Existence is self-evident and demonstrable; “God” is neither. Physical constants like the speed of light are not assumed—they’re measured. God, here, is not discovered but declared.
The essay casts God as the only escape from epistemic circularity, invoking Gödel as support. But Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems apply to formal systems, not metaphysical reality. Every system is by definition part of reality.
Plus, the very need of theologians to define gives the game away: we define what we already conceptually identify as real—not the other way around. A child conceptually identifies a dog long before he can define dog. Theology inverts this process, exposing itself as psychological projection rather than metaphysical identification.
Plus, you present God as a logical rather than theological necessity—which only magnifies the error.
You appeal to cultural consequences—as if moral or political disarray somehow proves God’s existence. But social outcomes are not metaphysical evidence. That’s emotive reasoning masquerading as philosophical insight.
You never define what you mean by “God.” Is it a personal deity? A Platonic form? The classical necessary being? A metaphysical constant? The ambiguity allows you to claim universality while avoiding ontological commitment. It’s a semantic smokescreen—designed to simulate profundity while dodging definitional rigor.
Saying “God was always meant to be the constant” treats historical utility as metaphysical proof. But how a culture uses an idea tells us nothing about whether that idea corresponds to reality. India uses the idea of Karma to organize its society. Does that make Karma ontologically real?
Ironically, this is the very consensus-dependence you claim to reject.
Why is it that no one treats existence or our awareness of its identity as a mere opinion? Because existence is directly perceived—axiomatically known. But God is never perceived this way. He must be argued for. You reverse this: you treat the perceptually self-evident as conditional and ideas as necessary. That’s epistemic inversion.
Once again, what you’ve written is a rhetorical performance, not a philosophical argument. It borrows the language of coherence to obscure its unargued center. Were you held to the same standard of proof you demand of others, your position would collapse—because coherence without grounding is just storytelling, and grounding without referent is faith, not knowledge.
This is why you avoid the axiomatic method. Because if you agreed to start at the foundation—existence, consciousness, identity—your reification, equivocation, and special pleading would become blindingly obvious. The line between metaphysical reality and mentation would be clear.
—James